The Categories and the Analysis of Virtue (and Vice)
by Dr. Jan Garrett
This page revised 9/29/2010
Aristotle's Ten Categories (with examples)
Substance Relation Quality Quantity Place Time Action "Passion" Having* Being in
a Position*This human,
SocratesTeacher of Baldness,
wisdom5'2" tall in Athens in 399 B.C. Speaking Being addressed has shoes on is sitting There are ten categories but some are more important than others. Aristotle does not do much with the asterisked categories. Among the categories, substance is the most basic. Without individual substances, items in the other categories would not exist; that is, there would not be qualities, quantities, places, times, etc.
Key words have different meanings if they apply to items in different categories. Good, which applies to things in at least four categories, does not always have the same definition. (This challenges Plato's notion that there is just one thing, the Form of Goodness, that we are trying to refer to when we speak of goodness.)
Substance Quality Quantity Time A good
human beingA good quality,
e.g., virtue, wisdomThe good (right) amount,
e.g., of confidenceThe good (right) time,
e.g., to do something
Some concepts are the same only by way of analogy. That is true of Aristotle's concept of potency across the categories of substance and quality (and across the sub-categories of bodily quality and quality of soul). The concept of potency in the category of substance ("matter") stands to the concept of first act in the category of substance ("form") as the concept of potency in the sub-category of soul (capacity for a "state") stands to the concept of first act in the same sub-category ("state"). (The principle is like that in mathematical proportion: A/B = A'/B')
This is important for learning. Suppose we do not understand the relationship between body and soul, or the nature of moral virtue, but we do understand the relationship between the capacity to acquire physical strength and being physically strong. Reasoning by analogy we can come to grasp Aristotle's theory of the virtue and his theory of the soul.
Levels of Description Quality of Body Quality of Soul Substance Second Act
Using one's physical strength,
e.g., lifting 100 # weightUsing one's virtue or,
expressing one's vice, acting or reasoning excellently or badlyCharacteristic soul activities
First Act
Possessing physical strength
Soul "state" or "habit"
possessing virtues or vicesSoul
Potency
Capacity to acquire
physical strengthCapacity to acquire virtues and vices
Body consisting of organs
We can discover connections between the analogous aspects. So, just as physical strength is produced out of the capacity for physical strength by appropriate physical movements (exercise), so moral virtue can be produced out of the capacity for moral virtue by practicing the appropriate moral actions.
Aristotle's account of how the soul is put into receptive matter is more controversial. He thinks that the physical contribution of the male parent works up potencies supplied by the female parent somewhat as a potter shapes the clay, with the difference, of course, that when the male contribution is finished with its work, there is an embryo, which contains an internal cause of its own future development. (The parents have no awareness of exactly how this is taking place, since it occurs out of sight.)